It is an interesting
and important part of any philosophical
estimate to consider the criticisms that
have been leveled against it by subsequent
thinkers. The most devastating criticisms
have been leveled by the scholastic school
of Advaita and the modern interpreters of
Indian Philosophy have made some additional
remarks apparently and some times have
brought forth new criticisms.
The claim
of Śrī Rāmānuja and certainly of his great
and illustrious expounder Śrī Venkatanātha
is that the Philosophy of Viśstādvaita is
the system which satisfies all demands of
consistency of thought, and Veda and
perception. It is a synthetic presentation
of the Nature of Reality as expounded by the
Seers and justified by experience in
philosophical and mystical experience.
It is
admitted on all hands that Śrī Rāmānuja is
loyal to the interpretations of the Vedānta
as given in the Sūtras of Bādarāyana. The
Vedānta Sūtras is one of the
prasthanatraya-the other two being the
Upanisads and the Bhagavat Gītā. It is
suggested that the Bādarāyana Sūtras is only
one of the many interpretations of the
Upnisads or the Vedānta. Śankara’s
philosophy with its unflinching monism is
his own rather than Bādarāyana’s says Max
Muller1. Prof.R.G. Bhandarkar
declares “There re two doctrines indicative
of the relation of God to the world, the so
called parinama-vāda and the vivrta-vāda.
The last is the doctrine of Śankarācārya;
while the first is that clearly held by the
author of Sūtras”1 Dr.
Surendranath Dasgupta is inclined to believe
that the dualistic interpretations of the
Brahma Sūtras are more faithful to the
Sūtras than the interpretation of
Śankaracāryā2. Mr. M.T. Telivala
writes “The fact that through
_____________
1 Six
systems of Indian Philosophy: Max
Muller, p, 117.
out the latter
portion of the Brahma Mīmāmsā Brahman is
described as possessing of some attributes
confirms the view that the sūtrakara has not
in his mind the jijñāsā and the
sastra-samanvya that Śankara wants to impose
upon him in the samanvaya that Śankara wants
to impose upon him in the samanvaya sūtra
1-1.4”3 “Kesavabhatta Kāshmīrin
after showing the contradiction between the
views of the Sūtrakara and Śankara observes
that according to the reasoning of sankra
there can be neither anything like jijnasya-
Brahman nor even sastra-rambha”4.
Books of the east Series of both the
commentaries of Śankara and Rāmānuja, holds
that the Śrī Bhasya of Rāmānuja is in accord
with that of the Sūtras while it is likely
that the interpretations of Śankara are
in accord with that of the Upanisads.
While it
is rather unfortunate that by this
controversy dust is raised between the two
prasthanas by a type of opposition being
assumed between them, the real conclusion to
be drawn is that the Vedānta Sūtras of
Badarayan is a great and excellent attempt
to synthsize the divergent or rather
convergent views of the seers of the Veda
and the rather convergent views of the seers
of the veda and the Upanisads, though only
one attempt among many. It is difficult
Upanisads, though only one attempt among
many. It is difficult to resist the
conclusion that the aim of Śankara in
commenting on these Sūtras was not
fruitful, as too many contradictions with
his views become apparent in the later
Sūtras.
_____________
1
Vaisnavism, Saivism etc.,: Bhandarkar,
p.160.
2
History of Indian Philosophy:
Vol.I.P.421.
3
Discuss how far Sankaracarya truly
represents the view of the author by Brahma
Sūtras by M.T. Telivala, Bombay. Cf.
Teachings of the Vedānta according to
ramanuja: Dr.V.S. Sūktankar and Vedānta
by Ghate.
4
Ibid.p.10
On the other hand, it is conceded that Śrī
Rāmānuja has ably given a monotheistic
interpretation of the Vedānta Sūtras. That
this monotheism is the real doctrine of the
Upanisads was shown by that great Master in
his Vedartha samgraha and by Śrī
Venkatanātha in the commentary on the
Īśāvāsyopanisad.
Dr. Arthur B. Keith says “The Śrī Bhasya in
substantial merit and completeness far
outdid any previous effort to find in the
Brahma-Sūtras a basis for monotheism”.1
Dr. Radhakrishnan writes, “Rāmānuja’s faith
is more philosophical and restrained than
that of his predecessors”, though here the
reference obviously was not to the other
philosophers like Śankara but to the Alvars
and acarya-predecessors of Śrī vaisnavism2.
The aim of Sir Rāmānuja as well as of the
Alvars previous to him was nothing less
than the most intense and or God Himself.
The philosophic poise rises beyond the
ordinary levels of values of Kama, artha
and dharma to perceive in the
Divine the source of all the truth of these
and thus interrelates these in the proper
manner in the Divine nature. Thus a
criticism that may be raised against the
view of Śrī Rāmānuja that it is partial or
fragmentary misses the main contribution
that Śrī Rāmānuja made to Philosophy, which
is precisely the axiomatic character of the
reality of all experience, momentary or
dreamy or deep sleep or trance or waking
consciousness or the divine consciousness
levels when consciousness attains or retains
its illimitable and reality-character.
Cjonsciousness gives reality; distortion and
unreality are due to karma and kama which
breed beginningless avidyā.
The criticisms can be classed under
different heads. The philosophical
criticisms are of course the most important.1
The relationship between the Brahman and the
soul and Nature is such that if Brahman were
to be the material
Cause of the
world or creation, Brahman must be
undergoing change. Śrī Rāmānuja attempt to
show that the relationship is one of Self
and Body between Brahman and Nature and the
souls, then the changes of state in the
latter do not affect Brahman at all.Dr.
Radhakrishnan points out that “Rāmānuja is
obliged to concede that Īśvara is a also
subject to change.” The change that is said
to be conceded by Rāmānuja is certainly no
such change in His nature, as would
certainly imperil His Nature. Īśvara
continues to have all the qualities in an
undiminished form which He possessed in the
earlier stage. The causal and effectual
states are distinguished by the subtle
condition of thecidacit in the
___________
1
History of Sankrit Literature: p.475
cf. Rudolf Otto: Christianity and the Indian
religion of Grace.
2
Indian Philosophy : Vol.II.P.669.
former state
and the gross condition in the latter. The
changes that take place do not at all apply
to the spiritual nature of Brahaman but only
to the souls in so far as some of them
undergo contraction in their
intelligence-function (dharma-bhuta-jñānā)
and to the Prakrti which evolves its several
categories of mahat, ahamkara, manas,
indriyas and bhutas. It is a
status of willing the projection or
evolution or manifestation by the Divine
Lord and withdrawal of creation which may be
said to be the change in the lord, but a
change of this kind is not to be classed as
the upadana or material change. This can in
no sense be said to be a change in nature,
affecting His status. The change that can
make a difference to the status of the
Īśvara or Brahman by either making Him
imperfect or involved in the process of
imperfection does not occur to the Īśvara.
Īśvara does not become subject to karma or
ignorance since He is the transcendent
principle, the self-principle which is
unaffected by the changes in His body, which
He Himself orders and controls.
Dr. Radhakrishnan writes that, “Rāmānuja
makes the finite the attribute of the
infinite which means that the Infinite
cannot exist without its attribute, nor the
attribute without the Infinite.1”
Firstly, Śrī Rāmānuja does not make God the
sum of the infinites. The infinite is
something different in kind from the
finites. It is a qualitative infinity and to
import a mathematical formula is a mistake.
The substance-attribute (visesanavisesya)
relationship between Īśvara and the jiva is
a statement of dependence of the attribute
on the substance. It does not follow that
the substance depends and exists because of
the attribute. Spinoza’s statement that an
attribute that an attribute is that through
which the substance is apprehended is a very
limited statement which cannot meet the
criticism of Dr. Limited Radhakrishnan. In
the system of Viśstādvaita, the relationship
is such that the souls cannot be conceived
as existing apart from God, and not
conversely that God cannot be conceived or
exist apart from the souls. God can be
apprehended apart from the souls in His
transcendent nature through other avenues
of knowledge than perceptionor inference.
Infinity if it be a mere sum of the finites
would yet be a commensurable number-finite
therefore, even as Leibniz pointed out.
The attribute or adjectival theory is not
the full statement of spiritual relationship
that he Divine, Īśvara, bears to the soul.
One should consider that it is an abstract
statement even as monism is, a metaphysical
abstraction that is a near statement of the
position. The soul is not a duality or
attribute or even a characteristic merely
but is all these, and more. The
meta-physical form of the relationship is
the peculiar relationship of viśesana to the
viśesya, the particular in relation to the
concrete universal, a particular that is
qualitatively different from the universal
because of its essential dependence on it
for its existence.
In this context it is necessary to cite
another criticism made by the same
Professor: “Brahman is not only a supreme
Sell but an eternal society of eternal
selves1”. The Infinity of
Brahman is not a sum of these finites, nor
is it a society of these souls or an ordered
or arrangement of these. The fundamental
philosophic point of view taken by Rāmānuja
is to present all the realized experiences
of the Divine in a synthetic form. The
supreme Self is transcendent, qualitatively
distinguished from the souls in their
severality and collectivity. But it is
related to each of these in a significant
body-soul maintaining them in an intrinsic
or immanent form. The supreme meaning of the
transcendence is brought out through this
immanent activity of the Transcendent. His
paratva is reconciled with His antarāmitva.
The Divine is one only in all His manifold
immanence in all souls. It would be wrong to
say that God in one part of His Being
intains transcendence that is to say
beyond change and Oneness)
____________
1
Ibid,715. (quoting with approval
Ānandagiri’s criticism in his
commentary
on Śankara Brahma Sūtra Bhasya I.ii.8)
whereas in
another part He is subject to change and so
on1. This is to functional
division
either, and certainly no metaphysical
division is here intimated. The Divine is
One and the many, the Para and the
Antarāmi in all creatures and Nature at
the same time and there is not any
separation of powers and so on. The
relationship between the souls and the two
poises of the Īśvara is through out he same,
namely inseprable dependence, and whether it
is society of nityamukta souls with
an interior significance of the immanent
presence of the transcendent within each
other or not, the Transcendent is
qualitatively distinguished from them in all
His forms or poises.
The criticism that the relationship between
the Supreme and the soul is not logically
determined when it is stated that it is one
of body and soul, requires a clear answer.
Any logical consistency in thought. It is
the following: Logic means consistency in
thought. It is the validity in a system of
coherence. It is or can be an
epistemological discussion as to the status
of the individual soul either as subject or
an object in relation to the Divine. If it
is a logical proposition, then there is need
to state that the judgment should reveal
that the Īśvara or Reality being such the
individual soul is the body of God. It is a
predicate of the Divine. It does not show
the inevitability of the relationship
between the subject and predicate. Logically
then the soul and Nature are predicate
terms. But then it is clear that the
predicate terms can be taken either in the
denotative or connotative sense, even as the
subject can be. Śrī Rāmānuja definitely
taken the relationship to apply to the
subject and predicate in the connotative
sense which makes the Organic relationship
truly logical as it includes the
metaphysical substance-attribute
relationship. It is because critics of Śrī
Rāmānuja have not really looked into the
significant modification of the metaphysical
relationship of visistaikya between the
Divine and the soul, that they have missed
the synthetic contribution made by him.
If however by ‘logically’ is meant the
necessary relationship of ground and
consequent or cause and effect which is a
special form of the former; and what is
necessary is the establishment of the ground
and consequent relationship between God and
souls(and Nature), then Śrī Rāmānuja,
emphasizes the adheyatva of the soul and
adharatva of the Godhead. Śrī Rāmānuja
affirms by his theory of śarīra – śarīrī
relationship (otherwise called Viśstādvaita)
this relationship o the body as that which
is absolutely dependent on the Self or God.
Necessity is now enlarged to include the
entire pattern of mechanical, organic,
psychical, spiritual relationships that are
available in experience between the One and
the Many. The relationship is not one of
illusion and reality, between the many and
the One. The many which are different in
kind from the Infinite One and also the many
which are but the self-projection, or
descents of the One.
It is to be noted that Śrī Rāmānuja’s
definition of the nature of the body is not
made to suit the metaphorical or
analogical purpose1. The
relationship between God and the souls (and
Nature) is not like that of body and soul,
but is the relationship of body and soul.
The śarīra is that ‘ which a conscient soul
supports, utilizes, and enjoys for itself
and that which exists for the purposes of
that soul alone’. Śrī Rāmānuja, shows that
the other definitions of the śarīra are
either too narrow or too wide: (i) the body
is nothing more than a congeries or
collocation of parts; this is an absolutely
mechanical definition which makes no
allowance for the self-activity of the soul:
(ii) the body is just something that falls
to pieces when the soul departs from it, is
a definition that again does to show the
self to be anything other than the principle
which maintains its unity : (iii) the body
is that which exists for enjoyment; (iv) The
body is that which has size, colour, and
other accidental qualities. We find that
definitions such as these do not state the
distinctive features to be found in the body
or omit the distinctive features or some of
them. The body is thus an entity or thing,
which be it noted,
____________
1
All metaphors or analogies have limitations.
Correspondential Realism which is that of
Yathārtha Khyāti, however, grants a new
significance to the value of Upamanic or
analogic inferene. The value of an analogy
varies form infinity to zero according to
the points of identity taken into
consideration or the evaluation of the
similarity.
may also be
a conscient thing, which another conscient
self, supports, controls, enjoys for its own
purposes and which exists as such controls,
enjoys for its own purposes and which exists
as such for such purposes, of that soul.
Thus the unity of the body is maintained,
its activities controlled or directed, its
pleasures and pins enjoyed and all exist for
the experience of the soul. It is true that
this relationship of body can last only as
long as the soul does the functions of
supporting, controlling and enjoying it.
Minus the soul, the body is not a body
whatever else it may become.
Śrī Rāmānuja thus in his concept of the
śarīra includes the concepts of visesana,
and prākara. His concept is not less logical
but more truly logical.
Again another consideration compels
attention. The evolutionary theory is a
modern discovery. The ancients believed in
the actual possession of tile sheaths or
kosas, viz. annamāyā, prānamāyā, manomāyā,
and vijñānāmāyā kosas. The moderns know of
the material, the vital, the psychical, and
spiritual levels.
In another form we know of the bonal,
muscular, neural and harmonic organic
structures within the body. The organic
changes here are interactionistic and
inter-dependent, but hierachically arranged.
The neural system controls almost all the
other physiological functions. So too the
vijñānāmāyā controls the lower levels and
the spiritual controls and directs all. The
lower sheaths, and organs, are subordinated
to those about it. A more highly developed
body means that which is controlled by the
higher level implicit within it or directing
it. In yoga it is this integration that is
sought after. When the soul-nature begins to
control, support and enjoy, then the body
and soul are recognized as two distincts in
unity. Śrī Rāmānuja shows that the concept
of śarīra-sarari relationship is valuable of
course not only between God and Nature, but
also between God and the souls. The body and
soul relationship between the soul and
portions of Nature is of temporary nature
because the soul is not fundamentally
controlling and supporting the body it has,
thanks to the limitations of avidyā and
karma. The Divine Lord not being subject to
avidyā and karma is the ultimate Organic
Self of the World and souls which are His
body. This view is intelligible, and is
religiously nd occultly possibility of
becoming the embodiment of the Divine within
and incidentally of erecting an immortal
natural body of the Divine in and through
oneself.
Viewed as a causal relation, the two
persisting under the stress of unity changes
in the organism, the appetitions and
perceptions and evolutions. All changes
emerge within the organism, not as
imperfections but as expressions and
manifestations of Divine will.
Dr. Radhakrishanan says that it is
impossible to reconcile the double status of
the Brahman as changeless and transcendent
with the temporal creative process of the
world. “If the Absolute is supposed to be a
transcendent changeless existence, it is a
problem how such an Absolute which has no
history, includes the time-process and the
evolution of the world; unless Rāmānuja is
willing to explain away he immutable
perfection and the Absolute and substitute
for it a perpetually changing process, a
sort of progressing perfection, he cannot
give us any satisfactory explanation of the
revelation of the soul or the Absolute to
its body”.1
The
reality of religion requires of God not
merely a double poisee but even a quintuple
poise as Śrī Rāmānuja pointed out. The
understanding of the relationship between
these poises of the Infinite Godhead or the
Absolute which retains its fundamental
quality of Unity and transcendence is then a
necessity. If changelessness means only
non-activity of any kind, and if change
means only imperfection or an effort to
become more perfect, then these are purely
arbitrary interpretations. To be perfect
does not means to be inactive as well.
Existence presents both possibilities and in
the Divine existence or Being,
changelessness means only no change
towards imperfection or diminution or
loss. That is the
__________
1Indian
Philosophy, Vol.II
reason why
the Īśāvāsyopanisad beautifully states that
the Full remains Full in every expression
and manifestation revealing the qualitative
distinguishing characteristic of Divine
Transcendence. The Transcendence is
absolute because it is equally
transcendent in immanence, in manifestation
and in historical descent and iconic
presence. The question of History can again
be nothing like what Dr. Radhakrishnan
thinks it should be. The problem is not
explained away. The inconveniences are all
Dr. Radhakrishnan’s. The real trouble with
the Absolutist Mind is its inability to see
the rich possibility of any other method of
significance, to understand the terms of
other philosophers. Dr. Radhakrishnan is not
clear as to the meaning of the words
‘changeless’, ‘Immutable’, ‘perfection’ and
‘history’, in the passage quoted above. For
Rāmānuja changeless means that there is no
change in nature as spiritual in the Lord or
Isvra and as omniscient creator, and
omnipotent knowledge. And immutable
perfection means the dynamic un-diminishing
deity realizable as the most perfect and
satisfying without any possible return to
imperfection, which grows in satisfying ness
to the soul and does not tend to become
monotonous or familiar. In Plato’s language
“The deity is morally immutable but not
immutability”.
A criticism against the too much
historical-mindedness of Śrī Rāmānuja is
made by a student of Aurobindonian thought.
He remarks that Śrī Rāmānuja’s system
commits the mistake of exaggerating or
emphasizing the play of the One in the many,
at the expense of the other self poise of
the One beyond the many.1 The
function of religion is the principle of
recognition of the one central personality
in relation to the individual souls. Thus
naturally the interest of the seeker or
mumuksu is to know all about the poises of
the Divine in relation to the world and the
souls, and more primarily the latter. That
Śrī Rāmānuja was not ablivious of the
self-poise of the Brahman in His Para or
inexpressible, indescribable, transcosmic
form is quite effectively shown by the
emphasis that the makes of that
Transcendence over every heya-guna and his
emphasis of the Ananta-kalyāna-guna. It
would be unjust to say that he emphatically
criticized was that the Brahman’s
transcendence should be characterized as
characterless and qualitiless. The question
may be reduced to one of terminological
difference, but it has all the importance
for the religio-mystical consciousness.
Professor Hiriyanna writes that the concept
of aprthaksiddha is meaningless. He says “If
samavāya tries to unite what are
supposed to be distinct, the aprthaksiddhi
tries to separate what are supposed tot be
one”.1 This criticism is without
point. Samavāya relationship in Vaisesika
Philosophy is inseparable conjunction
between substance and quality, and
individual and jati etc. It is translated as
inherence. It is conceived as a category and
it exists between a whole and its parts
also. The causal relationship is also said
to be one of samavāya as found in
the classification of a type of karana as
samavāya-krana. The whole analysis of
Vaisesika is atomistic and analytical. The
aprthaksiddhi relation however seeks to
extend the scope of the samavāya-siddhi.
Samavāya is mechanical and it has been
strenuously criticized as requiring another
samavāya and so on. It suffers from
the fallacy of infinite regress. But the
aprthaksiddhi relation does not need any
such third entity. All that this concept
shows is that there is absence of
separate existence. God and the soul are
inconceivable apart from one another.
Another point to be noted is that here the
relationship is between entities or
existences and not metaphysical categories.
The fundamental principle of this assertion
is the experience of existential unity of
two persons, one higher and another lower,
one an infinite, vibhu, and another finite,
anu.
Regarding the explanation of the illusion
which happens to the individual soul when it
perceptually identifies a rope with a snake,
a colour of the rose with the crystal, or
when the finite is identified with the
Infinite, body with the soul or vice-versa,
Śrī Rāmānuja attempts to solve it
realistically by a radical affirmation of
there being some real ground for the
illusion; and non-observation or
mal-observation or indescribability or
self-projection or subject being mistaken
for an object do not explain it; the
fundamental quality of consciousness is to
give truth. Our ignorance or limitation of
action (karma) and passion makes impositions
or cross-references through imaginative
fusion or comparisons. Comparison being as
much an intellectual process we have to find
out the real intrinsic nature of the
presented content, since however meager the
similarity between any two, at moments this
meagerness gains great dimension even like a
short man gaining great status under certain
conditions. Thus Śrī Rāmānuja is a radical
empiricist and traditionalist and realist
and has fundamental faith in the reality of
experience whether waking or dreaming or
deep sleep. All that he points out is that
real objectivity of the consciousness which
results from a life devoted to the seeing of
the Divine as the self and author and agent
of all processes and personalities would
present all in their true or real nature.
Dreams as well as psychic states and
experiences of objects which are similar
would not lead to illusion but to the
understanding of the real tattva of each.
Śrī Rāmānuja therefore being a fundamental
realist, accepts the reality of all
experience for the purpose of integral
understanding which would guide us through
the wonderful manifoldness of the Unity of
God and His omniscient power, omnipotent
knowledge and omni-embracive goodness.
The concept of dharma-bhuta-knana is
another point which is unique to the
doctrine of Śrī Rāmānuja. It is not a
quality merely but something which is
capable of increase to the infinite
extension as well as decrease to nullity. It
is a dynamic property as well. All that
happens to a soul in its freedom is its
unconditioned freedom from all limitations
and in bondage complete or more or less
complete conditionedness. If the self is
said to be consciousness. If the self is
said to be consciousness itself and that it
is both an activity of knowing and
______________
1
Dr.S.C. Chatterjee (Vednta Kesari 1942)
points out that if knowledge is quality,
it cannot give an ‘ideal reference’.
Knowledge is an intermediate between quality
and
activity, says Reid. Knowledge as Dharma is
an activity, which combines both quality and
activity and as memory conserving it, it is
also a retainer of the results of activity.
object of
knowing and also the subject of knowing,
then it would be necessary to make its
transcendence which issues out into the
three forms mentioned.1 Such
difficulties
could be avoided if it is stated clearly
that a self has the property of knowing
which grants knowledge of objects or itself
to itself. This may not be suitable to
idealism or absolute monism. All souls have
this functional consciousness though
themselves known and experienced as
substantive consciousness. The Humean or
Buddhistic criticism that we never come
across either a substance or self apart from
the qualities or states of consciousness
such as perceptions, imaginations, feelings
and etc., would be valid within limits. But
in the presence of the experiences of those
who have glimpsed their souls as
self-luminous, substantive, immortal and
integral with the Divine who again is known
and entered into, their statements can be
said to be true only of the pragmatic
emotional soul that is yet identified with
the bodily states of feelings and notions
and perceptions.
The last criticism to which we may now turn
is that the Viśstādvaitic view is not
sufficiently synthetic or synoptic. Does it
not forget the utterance that God is all –
sarvam khalvidam Brahama? The
assertion of the three entities is something
that is not true to it. Perhaps the
reduction of Nature and souls to real
statuses of the One supreme Brahman as Śrī
Aurobindo does is more satisfactory. It is
however clear in the system of Śrī Rāmānuja
that God’s inseparable relationship of
controlling, and directing and enjoying
Nature and souls is equivalent to the
assertion of the Allness of the Divine
Godhead and this does more justice to the
realities of the world and souls and their
fundamental existence has regard to the
infinity of God and His mysterious wonderful
ineffable nature.
_________
1Outlines
of Indian Philosophy,
p. 410 cf. Śrī Bhasya II.i.12.