3.1 A CRITIQUE OF THE PRAMANAS
I am deeply
grateful to the Executive Committee of the
Indian Philosophical Congress for having
selected me to preside over the deliberations
of the Logic and Metaphysics section of the
Congress which is being held in Benares, the
heart of spiritual India, and in the University
founded by the revered saint Pandit Madam Mohan
Malaviya and now guided by the great and eminent
philosopher Dr.Radhakrishnan.
It is usual at
this section for most presidents to give learned
disquisitions on the metaphysical progress
during the year or to describe the status of
logical enquiries. Sometimes they have given
enstructive hypotheses which revealed the
contributions and modifications necessitated by
the growing volume of knowledge. It is not my
purpose here to make any such metaphysical
speculation or give any metaphysical solution to
our ever-recurring problems. It seems rather
that a more modest effect is called for at this
juncture.
We have met there
in this most venerable City of Benares after the
attainment of India Independence. This fact
casts on us a very responsible task and that is
the recovery of the initiative in matters
spiritual and metaphysical, for even today
Benares is the nerve centre of logical thinking,
haloed by the debates of masters of logic and
saints of knowledge, warriors of truth and
servants of light. And real integral universal
thought is indeed the only force that can be
liberator of mankind. That is the task set
before us who are considered to be the
metaphysicians of the Earth.
Philosophy and
metaphysics are above the battle, the changing
fortunes of political and economic studies,
which are tied to practical and particular
interests and pragmatic arrangements based on
trial and error, which more often than not are
cur away from the unity of the whole. Philosophy
or metaphysics must be the basic ground of all
understandings of science of social endeavour.
Or else we shall go onwitnessing aberrations of
emotion and sentiments and encroachments on the
freedom of the individual and on the spontaneity
that is the characteristic of the Whole.
What is needed
today is a different emphasis on the points
view, a different approach from what we have
been habituated to and are being habituated to
by the strong impetus of materialism, fortified
by the success of amazing science. We have not
yet begun to arrive at a cordinating activity of
our intellect or consciousness. In recent years,
thanks to the serious impacts of psychology and
para-pscyhology, we have come to recognize that
the hard and fast divisions that have marked our
philosophical attitudes are being blurred. Yet
it is also true that whilst considerable efforts
have been made to make philosophical
constructions which have dominant scientific
methods, there have also come into existence
extreme abstract mathematical formualtions of
thought called by the common name symbolic
Logic, which is claimed to make our thought and
view of reality really scientific and to afford
a trauer picture of the structure of thought.
Such abstract constructions or formal principles
have truth, as Professor A. N. Whitehead
remarked though not the whole truth. But why
should it be so? Is it likely that there is some
truth about our intellectual aware that
intellect and its reasoning are incapable of
understanding certain aspects of experience.
Intellect seems to be quite adequate for all the
purposes of objective enquiry or objective
knowledge, as sciences have been showing to us.
It is true that neither the ideal of science not
that of philosophy as defined by idealists of
the objectivists schools who considered to be
truly of the scientifical approach and
explanation of the mechanical variety the only
admissioble category of explanation, we are
almost at the end of our philosophical pursuit,
not because it is completed but because it has
to wait on the experiences and explanations of
the scientists. But this movement of thought is
neither necessary nor inevitable. We have indeed
over again to investigate in to the nature of
our experience. After Kant’s great and
copernican Critiques we have been very much
anxious to explain our experiences on the bases
of the categories which we were warned by him
not to use beyond limits.2
It is
true that whilkst we wee well advised we did not
find it altogether to our taste, and indeed Kant
himself shewed that our experiences did overflow
the categories of Pure Reason3.
With Hegel we were enabled to traverse a longer
distance, perhaps steeper, towads our present
idealistic constructions but we also know that
these were evidently too formal and based on
dialectic of opposites which whilst promising
what is called the explanation of evolution
towards a grand synthesis or Absolute coherent
whole endowed it with an inner contradiction.
This inner contraiction may indeed be the secret
principle of evolution or dynamism. It is to
Mark we owe this unseemly revelation of the
intrinsic weakness or is it strength and
richness of Hegel? Who showed this up by
inverting the whole process and making dialetic
not formal but actual, nor merely logically
necessary but economically deterministic, and
historically inevitable? But what most
philosophers were concerned in the West was not
with the fundamental meaning of Reality that
could be constructed with the help of the
logical intellect refreshed by the deliverances
of senses intuition and the aesthetic demand for
an archetechtonic or system. We have also
witnessed our scientists becoming philosophers
and in the writings of Eddington, Whitehead and
Russell we have varied speculative adventures in
construction. At best sometimes we have been
regaled with ‘reinterpretatioins of terms whose
meanings have been absorbed in the counters of
thought’ – so as to make them current sterling
money so to speak4.
Indeed we have
enriched our modern ways of expression both in
respect of coining new terms in the place of the
common place and in respect of symbols, which
are intended to serve old relationships with
novelty. These dressings-up have been altogether
useful for they have helped the glossing over or
velling the problems of urgent concern. I do not
think that it is the perpetual task of
philosophy merely to present old thoughts and
problems in new grabs. It would indeed be much
more useful as an evolution in thought if we
could orientate our old thoughts and render them
universally valid.
But it must be
said to the credit of pragmatism that it has
found its best formulation in modern times, and
despite its human it has almost been forgotten
as a system of thought or new way, for the
business of philosophy seems to be according to
it the interpretation of the scientific results
which are daily coming to us, a task which has
to be perpetual if not exactly Sisypean.
We have indeed
another philosophical school, which is the
organistic conception. It is quite old in one
sense but its modern version is rather nebulous,
and it does not appear to be simple as the name
sounds. Reality is organism, a living and
dynamic whole comprising lesser wholes, evolving
within itself, whose parts are in continous
processes maintaining the whole. This is the
objective version. That it can have a subjective
version and that this subjective version is
mystical and more profound is the view, that is
held by many having unique points of view, value
and yet mystically interrelated with the Whole
which they represent, subserve, reveal or
manifest.
Our biological
interests have become dominant over our
mecha-nical interpretations not only due to
ourselves being biological results but also due
to the fact that the mechanical view of reality
which makes mere aggregations of points of view
insufficient even to explain the process of
Nature which seem to conform to the laws of mind
and life. The organistic view is much more real
and truer as a system than that. It has become
indeed a fundmental principle of explanation of
the perceived diversity and unity of the whole,
and in one sense has helped the refutation of
the unfounded charge of anthropo-morphism
against such explanations. There is no doubt
that pluralism and monism appear to be not so
much alternative explanantions of the same
groups of facts but two extremes of the
fundamental biune(?) Reality. Thus as it has
been recognized even by absolute idealists the
concepts of Organsism or Organic Unity does help
a fuler appreciation of the nature of Reality
than the abstract monism or concrete pluralism.
But it has been shown that this organistic
theory is yet in the process of birth in the
writings of Whitehead. The concept of organism
in his philosophy entails that the process be ‘
conceived as a complex activity with internal
relations between its various factors.’
Everything in the universe takes note of
everything else. If Leibniz affirmed that the
monadic mirroring is on the level of
reason(ratio), Whitehead’s view leads to an
emotional cognition which is introspective in
advanced organisms. His doctrine of internal
relations in a dynamic whole affirms that every
organism or a part of the organism is on a level
of prenension which is available to it from the
level of feeling not merely with the whole but
with each other part. Thus it is clear that
there is universal intersubjective intercourse.
Thus it is clear also that as long as our
congnitive nature is tied to external relations
of subject and object so long we can never
really grasp or solve the problem of interanl
dynamic unity of awareness within the whole. It
is true that some realists are content to be
mere pluralists and yet try to arrive at unity
by means of cooperative synthesis or unity by
postulating a ‘sense of community’ or unity
within limitations. This postulates of sense of
community requires a metaphysical justification
and it is found in the concept of organic unity
of all within the whole. The instinct or sense
of community that manifests itself is a result
or consequence of the nature of the whole rather
than its cause.
There is much
truth in the assertion that our inferential or
rationalistic thought translates into forms of
thought or ideas whatever it receives whether it
is of the material world reflected by the human
mind or of the spiritual. Our metaphysical
understanding need not coincide with the
dialectical process. Indeed all that materialism
has been affirming is that all the processes and
contradictions available in our concepts are
only the reflections, translations into the
language of thought of contradictions which
exists in the phenomena owing to the
contradictory nature of their common foundation,
namely movement. If then we can decide that our
materialism is but a partial formulation of a
further ultimate factor, the metaphysical
concept of Reality would become more adequate
and the manner of the Reality of such a measure
or nature could be shewn. The Contradiction
between the dialectical absolutists and the
dialectical materialsits is then resolvable by
the transcendence due to the higher perception
of values. But then we are again confronted with
the problem of human axiology, and we find that
despite Signor Croce’s formulation of another
form of the dialectic namely the ‘Dialectic of
Distincts’—(and that is truer to the spiritual
nature of the Real) – the spirit essentially
limited to the affirmation of its nature by the
human spirit or self. But we owe it to Signor
Croce who assured us of the fact that these two
dialectics are at work always, and achieve so to
speak a progress that is remarkable for its
double ascension in respect of the
interpenetrative unity as well as dynamic
progress that reveals the necessary polarity of
all movement, which in a sense comprises
horizontal as well as vertical possibilities.
Being and Becoming and Non-being are the forces
inherent in Reality or rather distinguishable
factors in Reality which establish the
interpenetrative fusion of the values of beauty
and truth and goodness in and for the individual
and the whole. There are perhaps other values
which are subordinate to this integrative action
of Spirit and it must also be understood that
this integrative action is one of concrete
Freedom. By this action we register at once the
continuity of the ideal purpose or action of the
Spirit as the inner meaning or significance of
all history. At any rate we are forced to
consider the importance of the relation between
the spiritual and the material as being somehow
established within the organic unity of the
embodied being, the individual who is the bearer
of ultimate values as well as the revealer of
the Ultimate values at every stage of the
evolutionary process, more or less. The goal of
absolute perfection is there and it is this that
makes possible for us to predict how it would
happen and when; but it is the inevitable
destiny of the individual, the task his
spiritual aspiration has set to itself. It is
in the individual that we should find the
fulfilment of this perfect unity of the
spiritual and the material (including the vital
and the mental); the subjective and the
objective, the being and the becoming. It is
true that this cannot altogether be due to the
inner aspiration of the individual; under the
concept of the materialist schools and the
rationalists, this aspiration for becoming more
is claimed to be inherent within or emerging out
of the avayavas (parts). But it is
irrational to claim that there is this
possibility in each of the parts or in their
aggregatioin as such. Rather it is likely that
this aspiration is a veiled movement of the
eternal purpose or the Spiritual from within,
acting both as an impulsion from behind
(sankalpa) and as an ideal ahead of us
(purusartha). It is in the human mind that we
find these two aspects of the same eternal
spirit uniting the aspiration and the ideal and
forging the perfect unity of the past with the
eternal present and the inevitable future.
Indeed as it has been stated there is the
descent from above and an ascent from below
whose meeting place is the human heart. Thus the
metaphysical view makes this the pattern of the
whole of Reality; or rather the individual whom
we know and understand will help us to
understand the pattern of the Reality of which
he is an integral real part. But this itself is
a presumption taken from the mystical doctrine,
whose pale counterpart is the view of the
similarity of all the parts of a compound or the
structure of the Atom or the molecule of a
compound. It is indeed not like that exactly
with each individual, but there is, as we can
see, the element of identity which is important.
This identity is at once the fundamental
principle of the unity of all the many and the
multiplicity which manifests itself in all the
many without undergoing any kind of essential
change in any of its characteristics, though
getting translated in varying degrees in
different planes of consciousness or
comprehension. It is clear that this double
status of the One Reality or the Self (to use
the organistic word) which alone can function in
this manner of a unitas multiplex
category is real, thought it does in a sense go
against the principles of abstract logic. This
is due not to impossibility of any thought t
grasp the inner pattern of Reality,- for this is
the promise of the mystics that we can know the
pattern of Reality though we may not be able to
know the content of it at all or completely
ever-but due to the habit of thought to be
restricted adapted to the individual in his
finiteness, in his sensory experience and
practical struggles with the environment which
are limited or conditioned by the ability of the
organism to deal with it.This conditioning and
limitation of the organism itself ot he
practical and the immediate utilities though
very useful for immediate survival, does indeed
breed conflicts between the several members of
the whole each of which has its own problems of
Survival, and struggle is the result. This
struggle is undoubtedly a part of the reality in
so far as the ascent to a larger point of view,
a sense of security, is concerned. But that is
the representation of the principle of sacrifice
which the logical form of opposition and
resolution represents or subsumption symbolises.
Real security comes from conscious subordination
to the transcendent sacrifice or offering to the
higher and the fuller and the universal.
Thus we must
grant that our assumption will determine the
nature of the reality that we are going to
construct. We have seen that the autonomy of the
inferential reason or the abstract understanding
has been most effectively denied by all alike.
Its sovereinty is overthrown, and mostly because
of its sensist affiliations. Whether we are
pragmatists or idealists or common sense men or
scientists, the regulative principles of thought
are no longer of mere reason. More likely the
regulative principles are of the practical and
aesthetic order, and decided by our economic and
political predilections or spiritual
institutions and aspirations and in many cases
by such personality factors that are determined
by our subliminal and unconscious being.
Metaphysics is not possible but it has been
forced to abandon the old routes of
construction. In being loyal to sensist
deliverances and hypothetical theories,
intellect has been strictly confined to the
construction of an abstract speculum (or
measure) and not as we should very much like to
have a speculum sub specie eterni.
I consider that
this would be an appropriate occasion to
evaluate the sources of our right knowledge
pramanas and offer a criticism. I deem it very
necessary that Indian philosophers and logicians
should undertake a new evaluation of the
categories of thought and especially make a
thorough study of the use to which the pramanas
have been put by Indian logicians. We have a
right to do it if only for the simple reason
that most logical treatises (of the scholastic
and suncretist variety) are much more concerned
with the analytical survey of these pramanas
than the synthetical, and incidentally there has
crept into their methodology a bias towards
materialistic and sensist understanding. I offer
on this occasion my remarks on this undertaking
with the fervant hope that it would lead to more
close and critical thinking so as to enable us
to evolve a logic more in tune with the
fundamental philosophy of Spirit espoused by
Seers of the infinite than before.
Nyaya as logic
considers primarily the prmanas, the instruments
of right knowledge. It enumerates them and
distinguishes them. Though these pramanas are
not identical, they all cooperate in the act of
knowing an object. The same object or prameya
may be the objects of certain pramanas or some
aspects of them be beyond some of these
pramanas. But it is the hope of every
philosopher ultimately to render all experience
integral, that is to say, to enable all
instruments of knowledge to function
synthetically without opposition or conflict, or
organically in one word. This is possible only
when all these are suboridnated to or directed
by mystical intuition.
Accordingly each
one of the pramanas may enable us to understand
some aspect of the object that falls within its
competence. It is also possible that there will
always be the mutual or reciprocal interaction
between these several pramanas, if there be more
than one, will grant fuller and profounder
meaning to the object in so far as that is an
object of knowledge, knowledge understood in its
fullest sense. It is just likely that certain
features or factors may be beyond the capability
of one or more of these pramanas. We have also
to recognize that no metaphysics or theory of
reality as such can claim that Reality is beyond
the scope of all pramanas; for that would only
lead to agnosticism. It would be our task to
discover that instrument of knowledge which
would enable us to round off our knowledge to
perfection and enable us to go beyond the
intellectual and sensory ways of knowing which
are either private or abstractly universal and
seriously limited to the avenues of our
experience as finite individuals. It is true
that some well-known thinkers hold that it
impossible to know Reality so long as we are
tied to the subject-object relationship, and
that Reality is indescribable5 which
is said to mean that it is either an experience
transcendent to all relationships or describable
as this or that.
Absolute Reality
as I have already remarked may be beyond the
comprehension of some of the pramanas that we
know of and utilize but that it is unknowable at
all is not acceptable. Indeed it I enunciated by
the mystic teaching that the Spirit reveals
itself to the individual chosen by it- tanum
svam vivrunute. It can be known and experience
and entered into.
What are the
pranamas? They are considered to be four usually
viz. Pratyaksa, anumana, upamana and sabda. To
this are added smrti, agama, itihasa, and
purana: some have added arthapatti. Fully
conscious as I am that you are all aware of
these facts, I shall not labour to show to you
the meaning of these pramanas except to point
out that each plays a definite role in the
structure of the integral experience into an
organic unity6
Pratyaksa deals
with the sensible aspect of reality. Pratyaksa
as the name implies is the knowledge that is a
resultant of response to stimulus. A
construction of a universe primarily based on
sense-experiences is impossible. Materialists
really7 posit
the complete objectivity of these sense
impressions and objects and without much
consistent thinking. Sensists are incapable of
constructing a universe except with the aid of
such irrational concepts as chance, faith or
animal faith, as George Santayana claims.
Confronted with private and personal and
communicable experiences they are not satisfied
with the mere deliverances of the senses. These
extra-personal experiences do indeed affirm the
objectivity of the objects perceived and
independent of individual volition. Common
experiences in a world is the strongest argument
for the existence of objective truth, which is
universal and of the identity or similarity of
the structure of minds. Irrationality is as much
of the objects however as they can be of
subjects, though we find their relational
thinking is inevitable and useful for all
practical purposes. It cements and systematises
all those parts of our experiences as could be
systematised and there is much that refuses to
fit in which the pattern presented by
inferential thought. It is ideal when all
experiences could be systematised, an ideal
without any conceivable end. Thus anumana (which
literally means that which follows) follows
these sense-experiences and becomes the chief
function of thought among us.
There is of
course the limitation of the play of inference
to the field of the perceived data, though this
limitation is in some definite manner surpassed
or transcended by the fact of similarity in the
experiences of objects and their relating by
minds. Whether we are prepared to agree to the
fact on the basis of pure inference or not, we
have to assume that mind-activity is alike in
all beings similarly physically constituted.
This assumption is important and there have been
learned but inconclusive treatises and
discussions on the problem of how we do know
other minds. In this context I can remark that
Sabarasvamin in his commentary on the Purva
Mimamsa sutras has noted that our knowledge of
other minds is based not on inference or
perception, though these two do aid us by
upamana (which literally means near-measure,
measure taken when standing very closely)8.
8 I.i.5. “Further through Upamana also this
same self is pointed out in the words ‘just as
you perceive your own self so on the same
Upamana please understand that I perceive the
self in the same manner”.(MM.Ganganatha Jha’s
trans). I have kept the word Upamana
untranslated.
A study or
Nyaya-Vaisesika method of approach reveals that
despite much clear thinking it is dominated by
the sense-order. Sensation dominates over
inference or relational thinking for the
reference to facts,correspondence of thoughts to
things, and extrinsic test ensure the
affirmation of material truth. The aim of
science is this much. This entails many
observers and mutual verification and
organisation of experience. Secondly, perception
gransts an objective world though of deiscrete
objects and with discrete sensations which
require a locus or foothold or ayatana, and
which in other words, can be described as the
unity of these qualities related in a definite
manner. These qualities are general, found in
more than one perceived objects, and we have
come to see that these inferences of identity
are not only of the general nature of these
qualities but also their interrelations, as
distinguished from those around them. They are
innumerable and enumerable. They are related
externally or in eternal conjuction in some
cases. Motion too is observed between these
objects as well as change of state. And thus we
begin to see even the relative non-existence.
Thus almost all the padarthas are perceptible
facts though doubtless they seem to involve
inference. These six ways of knowing an object
really refers to the perception of these
categories none and the same object recognized
the common objects for all. Samavaya,
inbherence, is also stated to be a percept,
though it is really a relation, because of the
observation of going together. The only point
about the Samavaya is that it affirms a
belonging together which is a category of
inference, even as the concept to vyapti or
invariable concommi-tance between two sets of
phenomena is.
That is why we
find that the Vaisesika darsan gives such a
realistic, pluralistic, senstist account of
reality. It realises however that the universe
of reality has other factors regarding he
subject of experience, oneself and other selves,
which are not perception-dependent. That is the
reason why it accepts inference as an appendage
to perception and includes Sabda under anumana.
Indeed the atomic theory, the theory of adrsta
and others due to inference and sabda. Its
acceptance of scriptural teaching is limited to
the sphere of the supersensible and the
supraconceptual dharma and Isvara. Jainism did
not accept the agama of the Vedic origin nor did
Buddhism. Buddhists accept inference and rank it
above perception and consider that thought when
relieved of the perceptual limitations may be
able to free us from the perpetual confusion
that is perceptual experience. Jainism is nearer
the scientific view, the pragmatic view of
dominance of perception over reasoning.
When we come to
deal with the Sankhya view we find that Reason
or inference is rendered more important as an
instrument of knoweldge and there is distrust
too of the sensedeliverances. Reality is looked
at with the aid of reason almost to the
exclusion of the perceptual. Perception plays a
subordinate role. Not so much the person but
reason is important. All processes of Nature may
be sensorially real but they are brought under
the concept of reason or buddhi or intellect.
It is the discrimination or rather the loss of
it that produces the sensible world. Indeed
sense-experience is a degradation or objective
extension of the intellect. The laws of thought
such as uniformity, causality, unity and
oppositional interaction are dealt with in
Sankhya. Substance is equated with qualities,
which are not quite the mere responses of sense
organs to stimuli. A new concept of quality as
dynamic, as combining at once the nature of a
substance and its power of effecting some
process or stimulation or motion is evolved, The
individual conscient being is distinguished from
the Nature and the realism of spirit and
consciousness are defenitiely distinguished from
the realms of Nature or matter. There however
seems to be several degree of their
interconnection. We can see the same first step
in evolving intellectual systems here in India,
as it was in the West, when sense was
distinguished from the reason and reason was
considered to lead to truth whereas sense could
only lead to ignorance. Undoubtedly, as Plato
indeed saw, sense may be subordinated to reason
in order to discover in it the reflections,
however plate or attenuated, of the immaculate
truths or eternal forms or ideas of Reason.
Buddhism and Sankhya are rational systems: but
Sankhya submits reason to the delivarnces of
mystic teaching. It is true that Buddhism also
ultimately ended in evolving a mysticism but had
to pass through a period of nirvana-experience
poised on the supreme conception of an
all-embracing compassion. The world-view granted
by Sankhya is a world of souls and a world of
Nature. In the modern constructions of the
philosophers we are indeed presented with this
same pluralism of souls united by, or denizens
of, of common Nature or universe charged with
the task of understanding it and through that,
understanding themselves. They have now come to
assume that in this dynamic process of
understanding they are organic to each other and
must evolve a formula of existing together in
harmony. But then the souls must first become
spectators of the process of Nature in which
they are organically involved through senses or
perception and affection and volition. Once they
begin to exercise reason and withdraw from the
senses and their objects they will regain that
supreme intellectual state of perfect
discrimination, which neither accepts nor
rejects or condemns anything of Nature, and by
this training begins to experience a new
dimension of Nature, universal in kind and a
truer pulse of Reality as subject-object. The
great contribution of Sankhya thought with which
we can compare those of the platonic-Socretean
philosophy is in the field of psychology of
Nature, the subjective aspect of Nature as
against the objective aspect of Nature, as an
aspect open to the instrument of anumana,
inference rather than pratyaksa, which can only
present the surface fact. It is this higher type
of anumana which is considered to be alike to
intuition, inseeing or in-measuring or valuing.
This is surely a new meaning of the term
anumana. Yet by this alone is Nature understood
from within as reality. By means of this
anumana, purified reason, Nature is not
apprehended as the Reality but only as the
subject against the object. Our inferences are
even shown to be vitiated at very start. Our
perceptive defect, akhyati (non-observation) is
shown to be the starting point of illusion and
transmigratory and evolutionary process. This
perceptive defect is not of the sensory order
but of the primary intellect itself. Some
thinkers find in this position echoes of the
Kantian schools, but it might be said that this
is a state of consci-ousness which is the
turning-point of the subjective-objective, the
crucial point when the subjective becomes
projective and objective or else the point when
the objective restores itself to the subjective
status, as Nicolai Berdyeav intimates. The
sensory knowledge that we now get is a more
distinguished and emphasised one. Reverse the
direction of perception from the objective to
the subjective or still better or another way of
stating of the same fact, substitute reason in
the place of sensory perception as an instrument
of knowledge, discrimination will arrest the
movement of sensory infinity. This is the
sadhana of the rationalists. Sankhya and in a
more radical measure, Buddhism follow this
course. In Greece Socrates, Plato and earlier
Parmendies and in Modern Philosophy Des Cartes,
Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant and Hegel follow this
course. Evloution is sensorial, involution is
rational; self is rational, nature is sensorial.
Sankhya is concerned with the self, the subject,
and the psychological core of being. Buddhism
abolishes the subject as merely the
configuration of ideas and images and as the
womb of all dialectical activity. But in neither
do we arrive at a true metaphysic of reality
which clarifies the fundamental problem of
One-Many. As plato said “Show me the man able to
see both the one and the many in Nature and I
will follow in his foot-steps as though he were
a God”9.
We are left with
innumerable number of souls within one Nature.
We arrive at the unity of Nature by means of
reason but not at the unity of the individual
subjects. It is indeed in Leibniz,-Nicolas of
Cusa was an earlier formulator- we have a firm
foundation of spiritual monadism which answers
deeply to the need for the fundametal solution
of the problem of one-many. The reality is
subject-objects, though we find that in our
experience we have to pass from the object to
the subject and understand that there is a close
correspondence between them, if not precisely an
identity in distinciton. The higher the type of
consciousness the closer does the correspondence
happen. Inference however universal a property
of subjects, is yet individuated and cannot
apprened Reality as a single whole. There are
two reasons for this defect (i) the constant
habituation in our life (or lives) of inference
to the field of Nature or understanding the laws
of Nature and (ii) the prioriy of sensations or
sense-action or reaction to the world of Nature.
As already pointed out Samkhya and Buddhism seek
to reverse these two habits (i) by constant
habituation to inner knowing rather than to
perception, so that ultimately to use reason
alone as an instrument of knowing. Hence yama
and dhyana, dharana and samadhi are utilized as
knowing instruments, which lead to samyama in
the place of samyoga. Supersensible knowing or
para-cognition results. There is
soul-sensibility of the integral universe as
against the former prakrtic or material
sensibility of the organs to limited Zones of
experience. Thus when pure reason is
releasedfrom the strings of perception, it
achieves two things: abstractly it begins to be
able to be aware of the pure forms or essences
or real ideas; and concretely it manifests the
supersensible way of soulseeing and release from
the limited and very conditioned existence and
deliverances of sensory experience. It rises to
the level of intuition, intellectual sympathy,
and over-mind consciouness. We owe it to Sri
Aurobindo who has shown that reason has upper
reaches; and professor Radhakrishnan has
classically emphasized this aspect of ascension
of Reason or pure Intellect to the levels of
intuition (buddhi) in his exposition of this
subject. It is here that we come across the
third instrument of knowledge called Upamana,
which some systems donot recognize, whereas
others have different versions of its utility or
efficacy.
Supersensible
objects are perceived supersensibly by the soul.
Upamana is used by Nyaya for the purpose not of
analogical inference as such but for the purpose
of recognition (of kind) of an object referred
to by a vakya or proposition. In the Mimamasa of
Jaimini School, Upamana means the recognition
that the object we see has similarity with that
we have already known or seen. It is of the form
of inference of the immediate type that A is
like B therefore B is like A. In these two views
we see that Upamana grants a place to the
principle of recognition of the see in the
unseen or unseen in the seen (supersensible in
the sensible), since both ways are legitimate)10.
But it is clear also that most expositors have
preferred the former than the latter and thus
made Upamana a sensist category. It is however
my point to show that upamana has come to play
an important role in the interpretation of
philosophical literature. The study of
Upanishads of the Alankarikas (rhetorecians)
11 is a
very helpful line of enquiry to open up a new
interpretation of this instrument ofo knowledge.
It is at the hands of the mystics and seers that
Upamana undergoes a transformation from the poor
analogical reasoning that it is considered to be
and just an extension of the inferential
reasoning. The celestial world of light is
opened. Gods and goddesses, processes
supersensible and results supersensible are
fully presented in this world of experience.
Purva-Mimamsa-darsana has to deal with this
extended world of the supersensible reality, the
higher part of the sensible, multiplicity of
gods and functions, powers and performers,
hymnists and sacrificers, within and without are
the denizens of this new world to which our
consciousness has access. The Upamana in
Purva-Mimamsa and in Seer-poerty is strictly
governed by the scriptural revelation in a
sense; it gets its sanction and authentic voice
from the supernatural wisdom of the seers. The
Mimamsist’s world though a pluralistic world of
souls, it is a world of souls who operceive
their continuous existence with the
supersensible reality arranged according to
grades and planes of being and perhaps with
distinct laws (rta) and powers and informing
intelligences. No doubt commentators have tried
to subordinate this Upamana, which is the
instrument of the knowledge of the
super-sensible, to the anumana, the
strait-jacket of sensory inference or reasoning
that is sense-dependent. But once we release the
upamana from the apron-strings of sense and
inference, we shall find that it immediately
helps us too know or intuit the inner nature of
Reality as correspondential, symbolic
supra-subjective having its own unity of all
grades and displaying mutual reflection which
alone makes for the splendid multiple figures of
speech that adornall great language and
literature. Language becomes significant, poetic
in the true sense of the term, which embraces,
encompasses all similars by referring to diverse
planes and points of view of the celestical,
terrestrial and subjective adhidaiva, adhibhauta
and adhyatma. Thus language becomes richer and
words gain significance and laksana and dhvani.
Concept develops or is recognized and is
dissolved in higher consciousness resulting in
or in being displayed in various metaphors all
of which are discerned as being appropriate and
as granting rasa. Knowledge in Upamana
grants ecstacy or delight and delight or poetic
sentiment indeed becomes lifted to the levels of
knowledge. We move along the route to the higher
realms of the supersensible. Reality however
rich in this form does not gain anything more
than the universal quality of organic
interpenetrativeness or continuity. Upamana when
it is utilised, even like the Upanisads, as the
instrument of knowledge becomes the instrument
of supersensible correspondence—knowledge. It
reveals the Rta, law Divine which is
supersensible. The Chandas is supersensible,
rsis are seers of the supersensible. Hymns are
supersensible. All these are perceived by this
new instrument. How very different from the
ordinary conception of upamana this is can be
seen clearly now.
Great poets
always compare the persons and phenomena of the
earth with the celestical and supersensible and
supraconceptual phenomena. Valmiki, Vyasa,
Kalidasa and others use upamas or upamanas in
this manner. The upamas are, of course, of two
kinds: one svarthopamana, that is similar to the
svarthanumana (subjective inference) which
reveals or explains the sensible by means of the
suprasensible, (this is Mimamsists upamana); and
the other pararthopamana, similar to the
parathanumana (inference for others) which
reveals or explains the supersensible by means
of the sensible. (This is the Naiyayika
upamana). Upamanas grant knowledge as well as
delight that is due to the discovery of the
fundamental though manifold identity.12 The
Upamanas of Kalidasa form and interesting study.
He uses all kinds which make us feel the oneness
of all things in and through their variegated
diversity. The opening lines of the
Raghuvamsa: ‘vagarthaviva samprktau’
reveals the high seriousness, a characteristic
of great poetry. Even the Balakanda of
Valmiki’s Ramayana abounds in the upamanas
which reveal the characteristic of great poetry
to lie in this transference of sensory images to
the supersensory and more importanlty the
application of the supersensory to the sensory.
The characteristic of seer poetry seems to lie
not so much in its being a ‘criticism of life’
but in this establishment of the continuity and
correspondential identity between the
supersensible and the sensible, which uplifts
the sensible from its inchoateness to the sense
of its truth in the Infinite. Thus also Milton’s
What if
earth
Be
but the shadow of Heaven
Or shelley’s
magnificent platonic
Life like a dome
Of
many coloured glass
stains the white radiance of eternity.
Instances can be
multiplied to show that this is the place and
function of Upamana to explain the sensible by
means of the supersensible and to make the
sensible truly the mirror of the Real, the
finite and abode of the Infinite.
12.
Upamana inculcates further the identity though
samandadhikaranya ofknowledge and delight or
rasa, fulness of Being , the feeling of the
Infinite.
13.
cf.Raghuvamsa: I .36: payovaham vidyud
airavatamiva; II 69.subhram yago murtam
irvatisnah. Etc… cf. Venkatanathe’s Dayasataka.
Cf. The poetry of Blake, Francis Thomson and
other mystics. Sri Aurobindo’s poetry
illustrates, this poise of the consciousness.
In the Vedic
Hymns, the Brahmanas and Upanishads the use of
the upamana itself betokens realities.
Suggesstion is utilised too in order to prove
truth, reality-Yatharthajnana. The
Yathatthakhyati-vada of Nathamuni and earlier
writers shows that they held the view that what
there is possibility of similitude there must be
some obscure or occult ground of identity, real
ground-knowledge is always of the real; whether
it is sensible or supersensible that is all that
has to be discriminated.
Thus we go beyond
the supersensory cognition of upamana which is
the field of supersensory intuition into Reality
in its richness and transcendent universality.
Yet this is necessary to go beyond. Thought
itself must reveal its real concrete power and
delight and total light. This is attained at the
level of sabda sruti the revelational thought
that includes the revelation sense. The higher
patterns of Reality are yet poured through
supermental knowing which reveals itself to all
seers of seer-like consciousness as the One
fundamental Truth of all realitites and which
also explains the movement and reflections of
all lower grades of the knowledge and the
‘ignorance’.
This knowledge it
is, that is, of the Divine in which all are, in
all of which He indewells, and from whom or who
has Himself become all these. This seems to be
the aim of knowledge- to understand the full and
integral nature of Reality of which all the
lower are partial reflections or representations
or snaches or ragged excepts for understanding
which there are several ways of instruments of
knowledge, All of them are necessary. That it
why the terms ‘ anviksiki’ does not merely mean
logical philosophy but also metaphysics of the
Self or Atman even as Manu held it to be at the
earliest times14 (Manu
VII.43). At any rate we know that when anviksiki
was used as subordinate to the intuitions of
supramental or the Infinite Self is fulfilled
its purpose of metaphysics, but when it was
later also utilized for the purpose of
understanding the interrelations between the
perceived which belongs to the same order or as
near those principles of the finite, it fell
from its higher purpose.
It would be apt
if I quoted here the words of one of our most
eminent living philosophers who states the
problem of our knowledge in this manner:There
is a fourfold order of knolwedge(i) “ the
original and fundamental way of knowing native
to the occult self in things is a knowledge by
identity; second is the derivative knowledge by
contact associated at its roots with a secret
knowledge by direct identity or stating from it,
but actually separated from its source and
therefore powerful but incomplete in its
cognition; the third is a knowledge by
separation from the object of observation but
still with a direct contact as its support or
even a partial identiy; the fourth is a
completely separative knowledge which relies on
a machinary of indirect contact, a knowledge by
acquisition which is yet, without being concious
of it, a rendering or bringing up of the
contents of a pre-existant inner awareness and
knowledge. A knowledge by identity, a knolwedge
by intimate direct contact, a knowledge by
separative direct contact, a wholly separative
knoweldge by indirect contact are the four
cognitive methods of Nature.” Saksatkara or
Sabda, Upamana in its higher meaning as I have
expounded here in this paper, anumana and
pratyaksa are what are clearly discernable in
above classification by Sri Aurobindo.
We are all aware
of the theory of Bertrand Russell about the
distinction between knowledge by acquitance and
knowledge by description. In the first of the
above distincitons drawn by Russell we have a
suggestion of an intimacy of knowing, something
that is affective or aesthetic as well as
sensorial cognition. But it could be clearly
seen that is a mere varient of Bergson’s
intellectual sympathy or N. Lossky’s intuition.
Both the above kinds of Russell’s enumeration
fall within the third and fourth kinds of Sri
Aurobindo’s expostition of the doctrine of
pramanas, according to Indian Philosophy.
Identity theories, though speaking in terms of
knowledge by identity yet fix their identity in
the general concepts or ideas rather than on the
spiritual or occult knowledge of the Self
which is more than the private self or ego.
Indeed if clearly conceived their’s is a theory
of knowledge of identiy (contential) rather than
by identity (as process). But then this
distinction is not usually accepted or
discerned.
I am convinced
that there is a sage truth in the dictum that
every unsolved problem or problem which has been
bunked or avoided will return to us for
solution. Reality cannot be avoided or escaped
from, not any portion of it will permit us to
avoid it forever. There is the urgent need for
taking all the ways of knowing which have been
counselled to us bymustics, poet-seers,
rationalisers and observers or scientists so
that we may be enabled to arrive at the full
knowledge of a metaphysics that shall not be a
partial representation or a mechanical structure
or an abstract configuration of the Real or even
a delightful Expanse of aesthesis. It is bound
to be organistic displaying interdependence
between the multilplicity, and concrete to each
individual in its universal measure. That is the
reason why we have to pass from the atomic and
the partial and the fragmentary understanding of
reality to the total conception of it. It cannot
be said that the total reality is an absolute
and infinite that cannot in any rational or
understandable manner be described to us. The
very fact that we strive to represent it is an
evidence of that possibility. We have to pass to
the logic of the Infinite which can justifiably
be able to explain the reationale of the finite
which refuses to remain finite, a refusal which
is represented to us by the forms of evolution
or development of our thought from the
sub-perceptual through the perceptual or sensory
to the rational or relational and to the
intuitive or para or suprarational to the
meta-cognitional which does not dismiss the
lower but assimilates them and grants them a
firmer ground or being in the totality
apprehended as Reality. And not only that – it
is apprehended as the most valuable or the
Ultimate Good and the Beautiful or saccidananda
which belongs to the self, the most real and
concrete Universal, which is the unity of the
many and their ground. Obviously it would entail
that this saccidananda self is the most is
manifested in and through the process or
History, which is a meaningful process.
The above is a
sketch of the reconstruction of logical thought
according to the logic of the Infinite and
according to the organistic conception which
grants the primacy to the mystic understanding
which accepts the dynamic units of all
experiences whilst not dissolving or dismissing
ant of them. This attempt is worthwhile since we
have so long sought to view the Absolute from
the standpoint of the finite individual and
failed to arrive at the solutions of the problem
of the Infinite and the self, and of the status
of the ultimate values. It is only when we
understand that the Infinite and Self is the
baode of the ultimate values ans is fact the
Ultimate value that we can understand the truth
of the ancient seers that Brahman is the Parama
Purusartha. We have a method of knowing the
Infinite, too. As Professor Macneile Dixon has
with great attractiveness and lucidity pointed
out the solutions granted by the poetic
consciousness and seer-vision, which we have
noted as equivalent to the upamana in our
exposition of the pramana-sastratoday-have
rendered possible certain definite scope for
further thinking. They alone body forth the
reality to the individual and reveal to him the
unique status of himself and the supreme
previlage of participation in the Life Divine,
the Brahman- the organism. Not merely the
content of the experiences of the mystic and
Rsis or seer-ports, but also the manner of their
reception has a large part to play in the
reconstruction of the Logic of the Infinite.
Indian
metaphysical thought can yet play its fullest
part as it did in the past. I have great hopes
that in this most ancient city we shall be
remined of our hoary past and the inevitable
splendid future and perform our duty to them.
3.2 SAMAVAYA- A CRITIQUE
SAMAVAYA is a word that
signifies combination or union, conjunction :
-intimate union, constant and inseparable
conjunction or inherence; it is claimed to be
one of the important categories of the
Vaiseshika realistic philosophy. They use this
category to explain the relationship between
dravya and guna and guna and jati.¹ Thus a
quality inheres in the dravya, blue colour
inheres in the sky, brown in the wood, and
viscosity in oil and so on. That is to say, the
quality cannot appear apart from the dravya, and
exists in the dravya alone. No doubt one quality
passes and another quality takes its place when
a black colour of the mud passes and gives place
to red when a brick is ‘fired’, which shows that
qualities inhere in a substance but changes of
quality do not affect the substance. So too the
jati or samanya (classness) inheres in a
quality.
All these
inherences are said to be of the same nature. It
is when the claim is made that all the
samavayas are one only that we have
to try to understand exactly what this means. It
means for one that all kinds of samavaya
or inherence are of the same kind and that there
are not many kinds of samavaya. For example, the
inherent relation between dravya and
guna is the same kind as that between
guna and samanya. It means simply
that if the guna changes the samanya
changes or a guna can have many
samanyas but a samanya can inhere
only in one guna. So too if a dravya
changes the guna changes but guna
cannot exist apart form dravya. This is
true of all kinds of inhering categories.
The inhering
relation can be therefore of two kinds: Eternal
as in the case of the qualities of the eternal
substances which do not change their qualities
at all, e.g. the soul being cit. But its
knowledge function can be temporary quality.
Thus the knowledge function is related to the
substance as temporary but knowledge-nature is
inherent. This is clearly a case of inherence (samavaya),
which holds together tow categories or even
more, since in knowledge we find many categories
are held together.
Thus in the
demonstration of complete definite knowledge the
Nyaya logicians propounded a theory of six-fold
contact, sad-vidha-sannikarsa.
Six-mannered contact is better than six kinds of
contact. Knowledge aimed at is definite
knowledge and in perception complete knowledge
would involve or imply knowledge of dravya,
guna, samanya, karma too,
and knowledge about a thing would imply
knowledge of its name (denotation) and in order
to be meaningful it must belong to a language
within which it inheres or which inheres in the
name, and lastly it must be clear for any
definite knowledge there should be the statement
of existing in a place and time. This last is
called abhava or non-existence but it can
well be shewn that abhava was a category
that came later than or as a reflection on
bhava or existence. This of course does not
make abhava an inference, for abhava
can be perceived as an absence of what was
previously present.
The
sad-vidha-sannikarsa has clearly to be
perceived as the development of the definiteness
of knowledge. Surely karma was omitted
for activity and rest were considered most
probably to fall into the
visesana-visesyabhava contact.²
There have been
early thinkers who did not think that we need a
category like samavaya. (1) Because
samavaya speaks the language of aggregation
which is permanent togetherness, (2) because one
would require a samavaya for a
samavaya and so on ad infinitum. Why
not be satisfied with contact (samyoga)
which is temporary and all relations between
objects which are temporary or between objects
and qualities even, it is so. Thus samavaya
is a category that we need not accept. That
everything changes and change means the change
in guna and samanya and so on, is
the view at the back of this criticism. The
question is, do we need to say that the contact
between the knower and the object known is of
the same order or kind as that between the
dravya and the guna or the guna
and the samanya or between name and form
and name and language (the earlier version is
between ether in the ear and ether outside).
There is an essential difference between the two
types of contact and we cannot say that
samavaya and samyoga are identical.
If samyoga can connect then samavaya
also can, but the differentia between the two
lies in the fact that in samyoga one can
disconnect onself from the object just like a
copulary link between two carriages, but one
cannot disconnect the dravya from guna in
a mechanical way. It is a metaphysical
distinction, not a mechanical disjunction that
is possible between the dravya and
guna or guna and samanya.
The criticism
that one requires another samavaya to
connect samavaya is a specious piece of
intellectual logic that does not believe that
there can be any connection at all, but a
characterless substance or reality.
One question
however may be raised and that is to ask whether
samavaya is not a kind of internal
relation as distinct from an external relation?
If it is an internal relation then is it not
clear that the terms must in a sense be so
related and modified by each other that when a
guna passes or a dravya changes
the terms would also get modified?. The
samavaya or inherence or internal relation
will bring about a contradiction in so far as it
has to fall away from one guna and catch
hold of another guna which means that
inherence acts as a polymorphic entity. Further
any internal relation is contradiction in so far
as it is fixed and unchangeable and no dynamic
explanation can be given. That is the reason why
in Idealistic metaphysics which accept internal
realtions as fixed we are presented with a block
universe. Relations are from a realistic point
of view clearly to reveal two kinds or rather
three : one, there can be connection between
object(dravyas), and this is samyoga;
the samyoga between a knower and his
object reveals to him that the object possesses
characteristics like guna which in turn
belongs to a class of qualities. The connections
that he establishes with the guna and
samanya are clearly through the perception
of the dravya-this is of course in some
cases modified-for one can perceive a guna
or a samanya apparently but no sooner
than he does so perceive he begins to seek out
the locus (asraya) or abode of these
qualities and samanyas which he had
perceived. Thus some thinkers say that it is
better to hold that one perceives the abode of
guna and samanya and the
description of this experience can be
samyukta-asraya. But one asks whether this
obviates the conception of samavaya. The
term asraya only shows that one
perceives the guna in a dravya; it
does not show how the guna and dravya
are related metaphysically-metaphysically
discernible but physically impartible. This
ideal conception of the relationship between
dravya and guna is dropped out. The
fact remains that we have to have a separate
concept for explaining this relationship between
dravya and guna : it does not
matter at all if one calls the relationship as
one of primary and secondary qualities and then
reduces all to subjective ideas-all these will
not get rid of the experience of the dravya
and samanya or even name and form and
name and language within which the former is
meaningful. These relations are not internal in
the idealistic sense of modifying the nature of
the terms except as factors of implicative
inference nor are they external in the sense
that they make no implication at all to
experience.
Thus samavaya
is a valuable category for explaining the
peculiar function of metaphysical analysis in
relation to the problem of relation between a
dravya and guna and guna and
samanya and also between name and
language not to speak of name and form.
However it can be
seen that samavya is used by
Nyaya-Vaiseshika in another connection. This is
in respect of Causality. They have distinguished
between samavayi, asamavayi and
nimitta karanas. There is another
cause known as prayojana utility or final
cause. The first samavayi karana
is so called because it inheres both in the
cause and the effect, that is, it is dravya
(substance) which is necessary and it is that
which undergoes change of state. Mud is the
material which inheres in the pot. Gold is the
material that inheres in the bangle. Cotton
inheres in the threads and cloth. This is called
upadana or material cause. Thus inherence
means that which is present in both the states
of cause and effect. Surely there are changes in
guna in the states cause and effect. The
efficient cause is the person who brings about
the effect using the cause. It is called
nimitta. Many cases are there which show
that nimitta also includes occasion or
purpose and therefore prayojana, may be
included under nimitta. The occasion for
making a pot or bangle or cloth can be
definitely given. It is the motive. It is true
that whilst we can give motives for the doing of
certain things, it will be difficult to give the
cosmic reason for bringing into being creation
or for Nature. However the reason for the
creation of the world will give rise to the
problem of nimitta on the part of God.
The asamavayi
karana is of course most interesting for it
describes all those causes which do not inhere
in the effect but cooperate with the cause (samavayi)
to bring about the effect. They are in the case
of making a pot, the potter, the wheel, the
stick, water, etc.
The asamavayi
karana therefore refers to all those
implements and ingredients (samagri)
which do not form part of the effect at all but
which are nonetheless necessary for its
production. The usual examples given in the
manuals unfortunately do not give us any clear
idea of the nature of the asamavayi karana.
Thus samavaya
would mean when applied to causality again
inherence which reveals the Nyaya-Vaiseshika did
not reject a kind of modified identity between
cause and effect. All that they claimed was that
the totality of causes (including samavayi,
asamavayi and nimmitta) do not
exhibit themselves in the effect, and indeed it
is precisely because certain things are not in
the cause but which have been brought into being
in the effect that it is claimed that the effect
is non-existent in the cause but comes into
being anew.
It is clear that
samavaya is a necessary concept for
revealing the metaphysical and realistic facts
of the perceptive and inferential order. The
term ‘samyukta-asraya’ can hardly be used
in terms of causality which is a factor of
inherence. Can we do without samavaya
because it is a multiplication of categories? It
has been shewn that the law of parsimony or the
Occam’s Razor cannot be applied in all cases.
Inherence in this limited sense shows that the
effect is not in the cause not the cause in the
effect in the sense of logical implication but
that it is more probable to hold that there must
be some substance common to both the cause and
the effect. In this lies the refutation of
Nihilism (sunyavada) which claims that
there is no substance at all and that out of
Nothing something comes into being. Logical
implication flows from effect to cause but not
from cause to effect, inherence being only of
guna in dravya but not of dravya
in guna. It is sesavat anumana.
Visishtadvaita claimed that samavaya is
not quite adequate to explain the relationship
between God and the soul and nature, for all
these are dravyas and not in the relation
of guna and dravya. Samavaya
was refuted in the usual way of leading to
regress and so on, and one must confess that it
was also shewn that inherence must be permanent
and reciprocal or not at all. This of course is
to demand from objective and realistic analysis
something that is not there. Change reveals this
demand for some inherences being temporary: it
is not perhaps necessary to say that all should
be permanent and none should be temporary.
The relation
between dravya and dravya as, for
example, between God and souls is said to be one
of inseparability (aprthaksiddha). So too
the relation between God and Nature is said to
be one of inseparability (aprthaksiddha).
This is on the ground that God is ever
exercising the power of control, direction,
support and enjoyment of them. In other words,
the constant exercise of power over the two
dravyas mentioned (souls and Nature) is said
to be logically being defined as inseparability.
Suppose the souls are separated from God; what
will result? In the one case the souls may cease
to be as also in the other case Nature will
cease to be. In other words it is inconceivable
that either the souls or Nature cease to be and
this assurance of their eternity it is that
makes us assume that God does not even for a
while cease to exercise power of preservation of
them. However, how are we to explain the
processes of change in the soul’s
consciousness-function and the Nature except by
saying that God with whom they form a unity (samavaya
or Oneness) wills the manifold manifestations of
souls and Nature?
Thus
aprthaksiddha sambandha differentiating
itself from samavaya does rescue the
souls and Nature from being mere visesanas
or gunas, for it firmly establishes the
fact that it is relation between real entities (dravyas)
and secondly the inherence is not of the causal
(upadana) order of kind, and that it is
permanent.
This is usually
lost sight of because some thinkers almost
reduce the soul to the level of a guna
and Nature to the level of trigunas which
because of this misuse or abuse of the terms
leads to various misinterpretations.
However we have
yet to feel our way to speaking about
samavaya as the principle of Reality as
basically governed by Unity or System or
One-Many. All pluralistic thinkers must arrive
at the realisation of the necessity for a
principle of Inherence or Aggregation and
Combination which will produce Happiness for
all. In what sense can this sense of inherence
or union be discovered in all and between all.
It is impossible to think that this inherence
can be between all individuals as such, except
by the assumption of a common bond of love that
animates all form within, inseparable from our
nature. This may be Atman or the living
principle in all. But is it the technical
inherence as we have met with in the Nyaya? No.
However Vedanta has spoken of this Self in all
and all in the Self in a sense of basic
inherence or should we better choose the word
aprthaksiddha? As it has been pointed out
aprthaksiddha is linked up with the Power of
the Divine, Cosmic Support of all whereas the
love that sustains all is of the order of
inherence, internal linking-but then these are
terms which are not adequate to describe the
sense of support and love that are combined in
our transcendent experience of the Divine and
the Bhagavatas.
3.3 SOME PROBLEMS OF
INDIAN LOGIC
I
Indriyartha sannikarsotpannam jnanam
avyapadesyam
avyabhicari vyavasayatmakam
Pratyaksam
( Nyaya Sutras 1-1-4 )
The knowledge
that one gets through pratyaksa or sensory
organs should be definite or determinate. All
real knowledge is determinate or definite so as
to leave no doubt as to the object known. It
must be yathartha-jnana and not suffer from
samsaya or doubt. Now there are two kinds of
perception therefore, the indefinite and the
definite, the indeterminate and the determinate,
nirvikalpaka and savikalpaka. The
authors of Indian Logic usually speak about the
six ways (vidhah) of knowing as object in
perception. The sense organ has to come into
contact with the object (artha). Taking
for example vision, the eye comes into contact
with the object. The relation between them is
samyoga, a disjunctable relation, for the
eye can withdraw this contact and begin to know
other objects. But the eye when it comes into
contact with the colour or form of the object
comes into contact with a quality which cannot
exist apart from the object or is in inseparable
relation to it (samavaya). Likewise when
the eyes comes into contact with the samanya
(general character) which is inherent in the
quality which is in inseparable relation with
the object. It is clear that these three are
stages in the determinateness of the knowledge
of the object. The perception ‘that’ is
nirvikalpaka pratyaksa surely, but the
second stage of contact with quality and the
third stage of contact with the genus (samanya)
are paving the way for savikalpaka pratyaksa
which can only become complete when not only the
object’s form (rupa) but also its name (nama)
becomes known. Thus rightly the fourth contact
is with the name, which indeed is apprehended
through sound (sabda). Every sound refers
to a thing and in one sense is inherent in it.
Non-sense syllables however gain meaning too as
they get used. In one sense we may accept the
mystical rendering of akasa as the organ of
hearing being the instrument of sound cognition,
and therefore the contact is just between the
akasa in the ear and the quality of sound got
from outside as being in the relation of
samavaya or inherence. This is fanciful.
What is rightly to be thought of in this
connection is the more fundamental problem of
the relationship between sound and form in
respect of objects. No object is adequately or
completely known unless it has both form and
name. The name and form are related to the
object as inherent to it. This is of course the
Vedantic position. Whether the sabda is heard
first and the form is perceived later or vice
versa, every sound is linked up with a form, a
non-sense sound with a sense-form. The child
exclaims in some manner and conveys its
knowledge of an object with a sound, and
thereafter continues to use it for that object
whether it belongs to the general knowledge or
language of those about him or not. Conditioned
reflexes show this possibility of association in
cognition. Therefore the interpretation of this
inherence (samavaya) should not be left
to the mystical and fanciful physiology of the
past. And further the relationship between the
samanya of sound (word) and sound (word) is not
to be explained on the basis of the alleged
relationship between srotrakasa and akasa. The
linguistic position would be that every word
gets fused or gains meaning in and through the
language which pervades the environment. No
sound merely exists in vacuum, and language is
inherent in every sound. Despite diversity of
languages which have grown up all over the world
a stranger is confronted with the sound and
understands it only when it is understood in
terms of the language to which it belongs,
whether it is of the animal or man or different
species. The relationship thus is inherent.
Language is inherent in every sound and every
sound is inherent in a form or related to a
form, through every object has different names
in different languages.
At the beginning
in the perception of an object we can never be
said to know it fully determinately unless its
name is also given; determinate knowledge is
verbal knowledge, denotative.
What the ancient
rishis thought about their apprehension of the
Veda would get a relevency in this context. We
know that God revealed the Vedas to the rishis.
The rishis saw them. They also heard them at the
same time. Thus every object or word got both a
form and a name at once. It is said that the
word (form) and sound get fixed by the Divine
Himself. No human being fixed the relationship
of inseparable connotation and denotation. Thus
the Vedas are apauruseya – not man-made. In
other words, it is not conventional usage that
gave rise to language—sound and meaning. Meaning
always refers to a thing (fact seen) and the
experienced relation or motion or activity, or
even the similarity of appearance and so on.
Thus the view that all words are expressive of
motion or activity may be conceded with the
proviso that all these are facts of experience.
The name becomes a name differentiated from a
sound (non-sense word) because of its being
coordinated with the thing as in conditioned
reflex. Languages, however much they might have
differentiated due to tongues being unable to
develop the habit of pure or accurate
pronunciation (primeval pronunciation), are at
bottom derived from the original God-given
speech. It is not to be disputed that there
might have been different epochs of god’s
revelation. For instance it is perhaps very
difficult to prove the identity of language in
Sanskrit and Tamil or their mutual derivation.
Nay it appears to be almost impossible. But that
apart, taking the general
philosophic-psychological question, name and
form go together for determinate knowledge. This
is true whether it is through the medium of the
indriyas (indriyartha sannikarsa) or through the
manasapratyaksa or atmasaksatkara. Name and
form, sound and vision, sabdapratyaksa and
caksusa pratyaksa together give us determinate
knowledge along with the perception of relative
position in space and time (through the
perception of abhava or non-presence). These two
are related to each other as Sakti and Siva even
as Kalidasa Mahakavi praised the divine
inseparable pair-vagarthav iva samprrktau
vagarthapratipattaye. The simultaneous
presentation of name and form
(namarupevyakaravani) is here given successively
in six stages.
It is not
necessary to accept another mystical doctrine of
sphota, of individual sounds or letters for this
cognition. Thus we show that determinate
knowledge grows from the bare ‘that’ to the
‘what’ which included quality, genus, name and
language. But even at this stage we cannot say
that complete perceptual determination has been
made. Thus the Indian Logicians rightly insisted
upon the spatial and temporal perception being
included in respect of the knowledge of an
object. We cannot speak about space or time in
any perceptual sense except with reference to an
object existing, including oneself. Visesya
visesana-bhava is the determination of the
spatial or temporal location of an object in
terms of abhava or negation. Negation is
perceptual when it is one of anyonyabhava
or pradhvamsabhava or pragabhava.
In each case, it becomes reciprocal in the
sense, (i) what was not has come into existence;
(ii) in relation to itself it was not it has
come into being (as in the case of effect in
Nyaya asatkaryavada), (iii) it was,
it is not now (in respect of bodies that are
transient or have moved away from their original
position in space or time) or (iv) one and the
same thing cannot occupy two places at the same
time, or (v) two things cannot occupy the same
place at the same time. In each case we know
that negation is perceived in respect of an
object (visesya).
We find its
occupation of a place is the qualification of
that place, a predicate so to speak. But more;
it is in respect of the object itself which has
to be defined as existing in a place or not, at
a time or not. But this emphasis again is not
made in the treatises which deal with this
problem of definitive or determinate knowledge
in perception.
No determinate
knowledge is complete, no perfect truth is
possible in respect of objects of perception
unless all the six contacts are made and
integrated, so as to give us the form, the
genus, the name and verbal expression and
spacial and temporal location. That this is the
intention of the Great Teachers can well be seen
in their insistence on all these factors in such
a thing as sankalpa, which is determination in
the performance of rites (vratas).
IItc "II"
Sabda-pramana and Logical
Proposition
Sabdapramana is
the validity depending upon the spoken word or
expressed language. It is verbalised experience.
It presupposes prior experiences of other orders
of sensation. It is not mere sound-experi-ence,
wherein there is just the perception of sound as
sound: the sound of a crow being perceived as
the sound made by the crow. It is verbalised,
communicated experience. That all experience so
far as man goes is such verbalised experience
whether it is for oneself or another goes
without saying. Indian Logic considers that
sabda is the fourth pramana. The reason is that
knowledge is not only from one’s own experience
but in certain cases it is got from others as
instruction. The quality and characteristic of
the instructor grants to the communication of
propositions validity and rightness.
Aptavacana is the statement of an apta. Such
vacana may be laukika or alaukika, that is
pertaining to seen and possible experience here
or pertaining to experience beyond normal ken
and understanding and possible elsewhere. It is
the proposition that grants definite knowledge
or determinate knowledge about supersensory
facts available to those who have arrived at the
mystic vision or yogic relation. Such knowledge
conforms to clear affirmations or denials (vidhi
and nisedha), imperatives and
prohibitions in ethical and spiritual action
being also of the order of affirmation and
denial or negation. Thus knowledge communicated
by another person through language will have
this first quality of determinate utterance
about a thing or experience, supersensory or
spiritual or empirical and pragmatic. All sabda
thus conforms to the pattern of affirmation (vidhi)
or negation (nisedha) considered
logically. Ethically or ritualistically the
affirmation takes on the characteristic of the
‘ought’ or imperative of affirmation or
prohibition.
The proposition
of European logic is seen to be identical with
the apta-vacana. Every proposition is
either an expression of affirmation of a
predicate or a denial of the same to a subject.
This is direct logical speech as different from
a grammatical sentence. The conclusion above
mentioned is re-enforced by the consideration of
the conditions of the vacana.
A statement (vakya)
must have sannidhi (nearness), yogyata
(relevance) and akanksa (expectancy). The
subject and predicate must be near each other
and not separated from each other either by time
or space. In other words in respect of truth
what is aimed at is immediacy, non-interval
between the predicate and the subject, predicate
being that which is to be affirmed or denied.
The two terms must be conjuct, near,
non-separate. The Yogyata is the question
of relevance, an expression of affirmation
between the two terms or negation of them of
each other. This is the only logical relevance
that we know of and no other is possible. In
other words, Yogyata gives us the
copula-nature of the vakya. And as for
akanksa (expectancy) this is a new factor
introduced for the purpose of the syllogistic
thought. The words indeed by themselves mean
nothing at all taken in isolation. All
communication or instruction or verbal knowledge
is expressed in sentences or propositions not
mere terms. In thought no term stands just by
itself. Thus when any word is uttered, the
questions arise as to what it is, what
about it, where it is, how it
is, and also what it is not, etc. thus it
is the process of determination of the ‘that’
(word in the vakya) that is felt as the
akanksa (expectancy).
The usual method
of explaining these three conditions leaves very
much to be desired in order to develop a true
theory of Indian Logic. The fact that the
ancient Indian Logicians did have a correct idea
of the conditions of logical proposition, which
should avoid all ambiguity and give determinate
knowledge, verbalised or experienced, shows that
the later Indian logicians did not develop their
explanations properly. This is frankly due to
the advaitic theory of knowledge that ultimate
knowledge is (and so all mediate knowledge or
sensory knowledge) indeterminate. We may well
claim that the Absolute Knowledge is
indescribable or indeterminative by our
pramanas, which are human¹. But the knowledge
that we have of the individual things, and the
expression of knowledge in words and sentences
must be determinate and beyond the criticisms of
doubt, ambiguity, manifold predication, etc.
Nyaya system rightly explained in its original
the conditions which the vakyas (propositions
of European logic) have to fulfil and they are
not different from what is seen in their western
parallels. Knowledge is universal, and Western
Logic and Eastern logic have developed almost in
the same way. True, the syllogistic pattern and
even in sabda there are subtle differences which
bring out the mystic unity of thought and
applicability of this apparatus of propositions
beyond the purely logical purpose of syllogism
as in European (Aristotelian) Logic, But
Professors teaching Indian Logic have to take
note of the need for orientated teaching of the
subject to bring out the most clear aspects of
ancient thought to the modern scholars.
Accustomed to parrot repetition even good
teachers of the subject have failed to see the
fundamental contribution made by Indian Logic to
a proper appraisal of the subject of Logic.
¹.
Kena Upanisad mantra II : Yadi
manyase suvedeti dabhram evapi nunam…avsjnatam
vijanatam vijnatam avijanatam.
|